Is God the author of evil or its helpless victim? St. Augustine’s answer has been the most intellectually credible and emotionally satisfying solution to this vexing problem.
One doesn’t need a Ph.D. in theology to look around the world and realize something is desperately wrong. The existence of evil is one of the most vexing challenges a Christian—or any person, for that matter—must grapple with. It’s occupied the minds of great Christian thinkers since the beginning, including St. Augustine (354-430). For much of his life he worked hard at a solution.
Dialogue On Good Evil And The Existence Of God Pdf Writer in judaism evil is not real it is per se not part of gods creation but comes into existence through mans bad. Existence: life and death, good and evil, our ultimate end, the meaning of all things.2 Since these manifestations of the human spirit have been present throughout history, we can say that reference to God belongs to human culture and constitutes an essential dimension of society and man.
Augustine’s approach was not just brilliant; it was practical. His insight is intellectually credible and emotionally satisfying in that it gives hope and offers meaning to the Christian trying to make sense out of life in a fallen world.
The problem of evil can be phrased in several ways. One approach addresses the origin of evil, prompting the syllogism (a series of statements that form a reasoned argument): 1) God created all things; 2) evil is a thing; 3) therefore, God created evil. If the first two premises are true, the conclusion is inescapable.
This formulation, if sustained, is devastating for Christianity. God would not be good if He knowingly created evil.
Augustine realized that the solution was tied to the question: What is evil? The argument above depends on the idea that evil is a thing (note the second premise). But what if evil is not a “thing” in that sense? Then evil did not need creating. If so, our search for the source of evil will take us in a another direction.
Augustine approached the problem from a different angle. He asked: Do we have any convincing evidence that a good God exists? If independent evidence leads us to conclude that God exists and is good, then He would be incapable of creating evil. Something else, then, must be its source.
If Augustine’s approach is fair, it prompts a pair of syllogisms that lead to a different conclusion. First: 1) All things that God created are good; 2) evil is not good; 3) therefore, evil was not created by God. Second: 1) God created every thing; 2) God did not create evil; 3) therefore, evil is not a thing.
The key to success here, is the truthfulness of two premises. If Augustine can offer evidence through natural theology that God exists as Creator and also that God is good, making everything He created also good, then the conclusion—evil is not a thing—automatically follows.
This is Augustine’s strategy. If evil is not a thing, then the case against Christianity stated in the original syllogism is unsound because one of its premises is false. The critical question is: What is evil?
Edgewonk is a trading journal used by thousands of traders from all around the world. Whether you are a beginning trader or an advanced, profitable trader, Edgewonk will help you make the next step with its powerful features and functions. Get the free trial here. Edgewonk offers the first and only journaling and trader development course where we help traders find out what it takes to become a trading professional. We provide a step by step approach that will allow you to steadily build your knowledge and improve the way you trade. Master all Edgewonk functions with hands-on lessons and challenges. Master all Edgewonk functions with hands-on lessons and challenges. Launch Version 2.0 – September 9, 2016. The launch of the new platform independent and standalone Edgewonk 2.0. Read here what is new in Edgewonk 2.0. Version 1.7 – February 18, 2016. New Sessions feature, easier scrolling in journal, added new Custom Statistic slots. 2.0.41 Resolution fixes and more Last week, we released a major update and thanks to you and the great Edgewonk community we were able to identify two issues right way. Today, we just released another update where we fixed the issue with the popup in the Missed Trades tab some of you had. Edgewonk 2.0 crack version. Edgewonk only runs properly with the latest Java version. You can get it below for free. Edgewonk is a trading journal for all markets and all types of traders.
Central to Augustine’s idea of goodness (and, consequently, evil) was the notion of being. To Augustine, anything that had being was good. God as the ground of being was perfectly good, along with everything he brought into being. This goodness was a property that came in varying degrees.
With this foundation Augustine was now prepared to answer the key issue: “Where is evil then, and whence, and how crept it in hither? What is its root, and what its seed? Or hath it no being?”1 To this Augustine answered: “Evil has no positive nature; but the loss of good has received the name ’evil.’”2
Augustine observed that evil always injures, and such injury is a deprivation of good. If there were no deprivation, there would be no injury. Since all things were made with goodness, evil must be the privation of goodness: “All which is corrupted is deprived of good.”3
The diminution of the property of goodness is what’s called evil. Good has substantial being; evil does not. It is like a moral hole, a nothingness that results when goodness is removed. Just as a shadow is no more than a “hole” in light, evil is a hole in goodness.
To say that something is evil, then, is a shorthand way of saying it either lacks goodness, or is a lower order of goodness than what ought to have been. But the question remains: “Whence and how crept it in hither?”
Augustine observed that evil could not be chosen because there is no evil thing to choose. One can only turn away from the good, that is from a greater good to a lesser good (in Augustine’s hierarchy) since all things are good. “For when the will abandons what is above itself, and turns to what is lower, it becomes evil—not because that is evil to which it turns, but because the turning itself is wicked.”4
Evil, then, is the act itself of choosing the lesser good. To Augustine the source of evil is in the free will of persons: “And I strained to perceive what I now heard, that free-will was the cause of our doing ill.”5 Evil was a “perversion of the will, turned aside from..God” to lesser things.6
Augustine’s solution has not been satisfying to some. Friedrich Schleiermacher snorted at the concept that God gave good creatures the freedom to do bad. If a being is perfect in its goodness, he held, it would never sin even if it were free to. Evil would then have to create itself ex nihilo, which is ridiculous.7
However, it doesn’t follow that moral perfection necessarily entails immutability. That’s a different type of perfection, a perfection in being. Schleiermacher’s objection confuses the two. The fact that a perfectly beautiful vase is capable of being broken doesn’t take away from its aesthetic perfections. In the same way, it makes sense to say that man was created morally perfect (morally whole or complete, at his proper level of goodness), even though he wasn’t immutable in this perfection.
The objections raised by atheist philosophers J.L. Mackie and Antony Flew are more substantial.8 Isn’t it possible that God could have created man immutable in his goodness, yet still have the opportunity to freely choose in other areas? Won’t man have immutable goodness in heaven? And will he not also have freedom to choose among certain options? Why not here on earth? Couldn’t God construct man’s nature such that evil simply was not an option?
Mackie and Flew are right in one regard. God could have created such a world. Freedom in the larger sense (the ability to make choices) does not require freedom in the narrow sense (the ability to make moral choices).
They miss the big picture, though: God would not have accomplished a second purpose. He not only wanted free creatures; He also wanted plenitude, that is, the greatest good possible. Plenitude—the highest good, the best of all possible worlds—requires more than just general freedom; it requires moral freedom, and that necessarily entails the possibility of evil.
Since all that God made is good, even those things which appear evil only appear that way because of a limited context or perspective. When viewed as a whole, that which appears to be evil ultimately contributes to the greater good.
For example, certain virtues couldn’t exist without evil: courage, mercy, forgiveness, patience, the giving of comfort, heroism, perseverance, faithfulness, self-control, long-suffering, submission and obedience, to name a few. These are not virtues in the abstract, but elements of character that can only be had by moral souls. Just as evil is a result of acts of will, so is virtue. Acts of moral choice accomplish both.
A world that had never been touched by evil would be a good place, but it wouldn’t be the best place possible. The best of all worlds would be a place where evil facilitated the development of virtues that are only able to exist where evil flourishes for a time. This would produce a world populated by souls that were refined by overcoming evil with good. The evil is momentary. The good that results is eternal.
What good comes out of a drive-by killing, someone might ask, or the death of a teenager through overdose, or a daughter’s rape, or child abuse? The answer is that a commensurate good doesn’t always come out of those individual situations, though God is certainly capable of redeeming any tragedy. Rather, the greater good results from having a world in which there is moral freedom, and moral freedom makes moral tragedies like these possible.
This observation reveals an interesting twist in this problem. If morality freely chosen can only happen in a world where evil is possible, then heaven will be a place where there will be no moral growth, where moral choices will not be possible because all the inhabitants of heaven will be immutably good. There is a type of soulish growth only available to inhabitants of a fallen world.
Two Scriptural observations lend credibility to this view. First, in recounting the great heroes of faith, the writer of Hebrews mentions that some were rescued by faith, but others endured by faith “..in order that they might obtain a better resurrection”9 (Heb. 11:35). Second, Paul tells Timothy that “..godliness is profitable for all things, since it holds promise for the present life and also for the life to come” (1 Tim. 4:8).
Both of these verses indicate that conditions in this life affect conditions in the next. Bearing up under evil in this life improves our resurrection in the next. Godliness in this life brings profit in the next. These benefits are not available after this life or there would be little urgency to grow now; all eternity would be left in which to catch up.
It appears that a deeper, more profound good results when virtue is won by free, moral souls struggling with evil, rather than simply granted to them as an element of their constitution.
Augustine knew that evil was real. Independent evidence (natural theology) was enough to convince him that God existed and that everything He created would be good. Evil, then, must be something real, but not a “thing” in the conventional sense. Evil is not a created thing, but spoiled goodness made possible by the free moral agency of rational creatures. Evil is not something present, but something missing, a privation.
The challenge that God could have created a world of free-will creatures immutable in their goodness is answered by the notion of plenitude, the greatest good. The possibility of evil also makes a greater good possible. God made a world in which true moral decision-making and development of virtues is possible in humans, manifest by persons whose character is formed through growth and struggle.
There’s a sound reason why God has allowed evil. It doesn’t conflict with His goodness. God is neither the author of evil, nor its helpless victim. Rather, precisely because of His goodness He chooses to co-exist with evil for a time.
Book Review: John Perry. 1999. Dialogue on Good, Evil, and theExistence of God. Indianapolis: Hackett. ix+71 pp.
In 1978, philosopher John Perry published a well-received little book in which three fictional friends engaged in a series of stimulating but easy-to-understand discussions about personal identity and immortality.[1] In his new 1999 book, Perry looks back to an earlier discussion among the trio about the logical problem of evil. Gretchen Weirob represents the atheistic position, and Sam Miller the theistic position, while the neutral Dave Cohen simply helps the discussion along whenever the main discussants get stuck. The three talk about basic issues related to the logical problem of evil, such as whether any theodicy renders it possible (although not necessarily plausible) that God and evil coexist, whether divine omniscience and human freedom are compatible, and how atheists can make sense of good and evil.
The dialogue is lively and entertaining. It is framed in terms of a friendly bet -- if Miller can convince Weirob that the evil in the world does not logically contradict the existence of God, then Miller will get to pray for Weirob's recovery from the cold which currently afflicts her. 'What's more,' explains Miller to Cohen, 'I'll say the prayer in the first person plural, that we pray for the salvation of her eternal soul.'[2] The participants are evenly matched intellectually, and generally respectful towards one another, although they also poke a little bit of fun at one another as friends are inclined to do when they disagree. On occasion, Weirob and Miller each also gets emotional or goes off on a tangent, but each is quickly pulled back into the give-and-take of rational argument. Such digressions serve not only add a familiar feel to the discussions, but to point out certain pitfalls that should be avoided in such debates.
I would have liked Perry's book better had he actively pursued such questions as whether free will is in fact coherent, or whether any theodicy is in fact plausible. However, it is difficult to fault an introductory-level book for not doing something it feels would take it too far afield -- it is sufficient that Perry acknowledges that those questions are in fact legitimate ones (although he has Weirob realize too late that she should not have taken them for granted). Perry has succeeded in providing a clear and engaging introductory-level discussion of the logical problem of evil, which will appeal to both new philosophy students and the average Joe or Mary on the street who has only a few hours per year to read philosophy.
References
[1] John Perry. 1978. A Dialogue on Personal Identity and Immortality. Indianapolis: Hackett.
[2] Perry, 1999. pp. 18-19.
Copyright © 2002, Mark I. Vuletic. All rights reserved.